用户:David290/Artificial intelligence
Artificial intelligence (AI) is the intelligence of machines and the branch of computer science which aims to create it. Textbooks define the field as "the study and design of intelligent agents,"[1] where an intelligent agent is a system that perceives its environment and takes actions which maximize its chances of success.[2] John McCarthy, who coined the term in 1956,[3] defines it as "the science and engineering of making intelligent machines."[4]
The field was founded on the claim that a central property of humans, intelligence—the sapience of Homo sapiens—can be so precisely described that it can be simulated by a machine.[5] This raises philosophical issues about the nature of the mind and limits of scientific hubris, issues which have been addressed by myth, fiction and philosophy since antiquity.[6] Artificial intelligence has been the subject of breathtaking optimism,[7] has suffered stunning setbacks[8] and, today, has become an essential part of the technology industry, providing the heavy lifting for many of the most difficult problems in computer science.[9]
AI research is highly technical and specialized, deeply divided into subfields that often fail to communicate with each other.[10]
Subfields have grown up around particular institutions, the work of individual researchers, the solution of specific problems, longstanding differences of opinion about how AI should be done and the application of widely differing tools. The central problems of AI include such traits as reasoning, knowledge, planning, learning, communication, perception and the ability to move and manipulate objects.[11]
General intelligence (or "strong AI") is still a long-term goal of (some) research.[12]
History
Thinking machines and artificial beings appear in Greek myths, such as Talos of Crete, the golden robots of Hephaestus and Pygmalion's Galatea.[13] Human likenesses believed to have intelligence were built in every major civilization: animated statues were worshipped in Egypt and Greece[14] and humanoid automatons were built by Yan Shi,[15] Hero of Alexandria,[16] Al-Jazari[17] and Wolfgang von Kempelen.[18] It was also widely believed that artificial beings had been created by Jābir ibn Hayyān,[19] Judah Loew[20] and Paracelsus.[21] By the 19th and 20th centuries, artificial beings had become a common feature in fiction, as in Mary Shelley's Frankenstein or Karel Čapek's R.U.R. (Rossum's Universal Robots).[22] Pamela McCorduck argues that all of these are examples of an ancient urge, as she describes it, "to forge the gods".[6] Stories of these creatures and their fates discuss many of the same hopes, fears and ethical concerns that are presented by artificial intelligence.
Mechanical or "formal" reasoning has been developed by philosophers and mathematicians since antiquity. The study of logic led directly to the invention of the programmable digital electronic computer, based on the work of mathematician Alan Turing and others. Turing's theory of computation suggested that a machine, by shuffling symbols as simple as "0" and "1", could simulate any conceivable act of mathematical deduction.[23] This, along with recent discoveries in neurology, information theory and cybernetics, inspired a small group of researchers to begin to seriously consider the possibility of building an electronic brain.[24]
The field of AI research was founded at a conference on the campus of Dartmouth College in the summer of 1956.[25] The attendees, including John McCarthy, Marvin Minsky, Allen Newell and Herbert Simon, became the leaders of AI research for many decades.[26] They and their students wrote programs that were, to most people, simply astonishing:[27] computers were solving word problems in algebra, proving logical theorems and speaking English.[28] By the middle of the 1960s, research in the U.S. was heavily funded by the Department of Defense[29] and laboratories had been established around the world.[30] AI's founders were profoundly optimistic about the future of the new field: Herbert Simon predicted that "machines will be capable, within twenty years, of doing any work a man can do"[31] and Marvin Minsky agreed, writing that "within a generation ... the problem of creating 'artificial intelligence' will substantially be solved".[32]
They had failed to recognize the difficulty of some of the problems they faced.[33] In 1974, in response to the criticism of England's Sir James Lighthill and ongoing pressure from Congress to fund more productive projects, the U.S. and British governments cut off all undirected, exploratory research in AI. The next few years, when funding for projects was hard to find, would later be called an "AI winter".[34]
In the early 1980s, AI research was revived by the commercial success of expert systems,[35] a form of AI program that simulated the knowledge and analytical skills of one or more human experts. By 1985 the market for AI had reached over a billion dollars. At the same time, Japan's fifth generation computer project inspired the U.S and British governments to restore funding for academic research in the field.[36] However, beginning with the collapse of the Lisp Machine market in 1987, AI once again fell into disrepute, and a second, longer lasting AI winter began.[37]
In the 1990s and early 21st century, AI achieved its greatest successes, albeit somewhat behind the scenes. Artificial intelligence is used for logistics, data mining, medical diagnosis and many other areas throughout the technology industry.[9] The success was due to several factors: the incredible power of computers today (see Moore's law), a greater emphasis on solving specific subproblems, the creation of new ties between AI and other fields working on similar problems, and above all a new commitment by researchers to solid mathematical methods and rigorous scientific standards.[38]
Problems
The problem of simulating (or creating) intelligence has been broken down into a number of specific sub-problems. These consist of particular traits or capabilities that researchers would like an intelligent system to display. The traits described below have received the most attention.[11]
Deduction, reasoning, problem solving
Early AI researchers developed algorithms that imitated the step-by-step reasoning that humans use when they solve puzzles, play board games or make logical deductions.[39] By the late 1980s and '90s, AI research had also developed highly successful methods for dealing with uncertain or incomplete information, employing concepts from probability and economics.[40]
For difficult problems, most of these algorithms can require enormous computational resources — most experience a "combinatorial explosion": the amount of memory or computer time required becomes astronomical when the problem goes beyond a certain size. The search for more efficient problem solving algorithms is a high priority for AI research.[41]
Human beings solve most of their problems using fast, intuitive judgments rather than the conscious, step-by-step deduction that early AI research was able to model.[42] AI has made some progress at imitating this kind of "sub-symbolic" problem solving: embodied approaches emphasize the importance of sensorimotor skills to higher reasoning; neural net research attempts to simulate the structures inside human and animal brains that gives rise to this skill.
Knowledge representation
Knowledge representation[43] and knowledge engineering[44] are central to AI research. Many of the problems machines are expected to solve will require extensive knowledge about the world. Among the things that AI needs to represent are: objects, properties, categories and relations between objects;[45] situations, events, states and time;[46] causes and effects;[47] knowledge about knowledge (what we know about what other people know);[48] and many other, less well researched domains. A complete representation of "what exists" is an ontology[49] (borrowing a word from traditional philosophy), of which the most general are called upper ontologies.
Among the most difficult problems in knowledge representation are:
- Default reasoning and the qualification problem
- Many of the things people know take the form of "working assumptions." For example, if a bird comes up in conversation, people typically picture an animal that is fist sized, sings, and flies. None of these things are true about all birds. John McCarthy identified this problem in 1969[50] as the qualification problem: for any commonsense rule that AI researchers care to represent, there tend to be a huge number of exceptions. Almost nothing is simply true or false in the way that abstract logic requires. AI research has explored a number of solutions to this problem.[51]
- The breadth of commonsense knowledge
- The number of atomic facts that the average person knows is astronomical. Research projects that attempt to build a complete knowledge base of commonsense knowledge (e.g., Cyc) require enormous amounts of laborious ontological engineering — they must be built, by hand, one complicated concept at a time.[52] A major goal is to have the computer understand enough concepts to be able to learn by reading from sources like the internet, and thus be able to add to its own ontology.
- The subsymbolic form of some commonsense knowledge
- Much of what people know is not represented as "facts" or "statements" that they could actually say out loud. For example, a chess master will avoid a particular chess position because it "feels too exposed"[53] or an art critic can take one look at a statue and instantly realize that it is a fake.[54] These are intuitions or tendencies that are represented in the brain non-consciously and sub-symbolically.[55] Knowledge like this informs, supports and provides a context for symbolic, conscious knowledge. As with the related problem of sub-symbolic reasoning, it is hoped that situated AI or computational intelligence will provide ways to represent this kind of knowledge.[55]
Planning
Intelligent agents must be able to set goals and achieve them.[56] They need a way to visualize the future (they must have a representation of the state of the world and be able to make predictions about how their actions will change it) and be able to make choices that maximize the utility (or "value") of the available choices.[57]
In classical planning problems, the agent can assume that it is the only thing acting on the world and it can be certain what the consequences of its actions may be.[58] However, if this is not true, it must periodically check if the world matches its predictions and it must change its plan as this becomes necessary, requiring the agent to reason under uncertainty.[59]
Multi-agent planning uses the cooperation and competition of many agents to achieve a given goal. Emergent behavior such as this is used by evolutionary algorithms and swarm intelligence.[60]
Learning
Machine learning[61] has been central to AI research from the beginning.[62] Unsupervised learning is the ability to find patterns in a stream of input. Supervised learning includes both classification and numerical regression. Classification is used to determine what category something belongs in, after seeing a number of examples of things from several categories. Regression takes a set of numerical input/output examples and attempts to discover a continuous function that would generate the outputs from the inputs. In reinforcement learning[63] the agent is rewarded for good responses and punished for bad ones. These can be analyzed in terms of decision theory, using concepts like utility. The mathematical analysis of machine learning algorithms and their performance is a branch of theoretical computer science known as computational learning theory.
Natural language processing
Natural language processing[64] gives machines the ability to read and understand the languages that humans speak. Many researchers hope that a sufficiently powerful natural language processing system would be able to acquire knowledge on its own, by reading the existing text available over the internet. Some straightforward applications of natural language processing include information retrieval (or text mining) and machine translation.[65]
Motion and manipulation
The field of robotics[66] is closely related to AI. Intelligence is required for robots to be able to handle such tasks as object manipulation[67] and navigation, with sub-problems of localization (knowing where you are), mapping (learning what is around you) and motion planning (figuring out how to get there).[68]
Perception
Machine perception[69] is the ability to use input from sensors (such as cameras, microphones, sonar and others more exotic) to deduce aspects of the world. Computer vision[70] is the ability to analyze visual input. A few selected subproblems are speech recognition,[71] facial recognition and object recognition.[72]
Social intelligence
Emotion and social skills[73] play two roles for an intelligent agent. First, it must be able to predict the actions of others, by understanding their motives and emotional states. (This involves elements of game theory, decision theory, as well as the ability to model human emotions and the perceptual skills to detect emotions.) Also, for good human-computer interaction, an intelligent machine also needs to display emotions. At the very least it must appear polite and sensitive to the humans it interacts with. At best, it should have normal emotions itself.
Creativity
A sub-field of AI addresses creativity both theoretically (from a philosophical and psychological perspective) and practically (via specific implementations of systems that generate outputs that can be considered creative).
General intelligence
Most researchers hope that their work will eventually be incorporated into a machine with general intelligence (known as strong AI), combining all the skills above and exceeding human abilities at most or all of them.[12] A few believe that anthropomorphic features like artificial consciousness or an artificial brain may be required for such a project.[74]
Many of the problems above are considered AI-complete: to solve one problem, you must solve them all. For example, even a straightforward, specific task like machine translation requires that the machine follow the author's argument (reason), know what is being talked about (knowledge), and faithfully reproduce the author's intention (social intelligence). Machine translation, therefore, is believed to be AI-complete: it may require strong AI to be done as well as humans can do it.[75]
Approaches
There is no established unifying theory or paradigm that guides AI research. Researchers disagree about many issues.[76] A few of the most long standing questions that have remained unanswered are these: should artificial intelligence simulate natural intelligence, by studying psychology or neurology? Or is human biology as irrelevant to AI research as bird biology is to aeronautical engineering?[77] Can intelligent behavior be described using simple, elegant principles (such as logic or optimization)? Or does it necessarily require solving a large number of completely unrelated problems?[78] Can intelligence be reproduced using high-level symbols, similar to words and ideas? Or does it require "sub-symbolic" processing?[79]
Cybernetics and brain simulation
In the 1940s and 1950s, a number of researchers explored the connection between neurology, information theory, and cybernetics. Some of them built machines that used electronic networks to exhibit rudimentary intelligence, such as W. Grey Walter's turtles and the Johns Hopkins Beast. Many of these researchers gathered for meetings of the Teleological Society at Princeton University and the Ratio Club in England.[24] By 1960, this approach was largely abandoned, although elements of it would be revived in the 1980s.
Symbolic
When access to digital computers became possible in the middle 1950s, AI research began to explore the possibility that human intelligence could be reduced to symbol manipulation. The research was centered in three institutions: CMU, Stanford and MIT, and each one developed its own style of research. John Haugeland named these approaches to AI "good old fashioned AI" or "GOFAI".[80]
- Cognitive simulation
- Economist Herbert Simon and Alan Newell studied human problem solving skills and attempted to formalize them, and their work laid the foundations of the field of artificial intelligence, as well as cognitive science, operations research and management science. Their research team performed psychological experiments to demonstrate the similarities between human problem solving and the programs (such as their "General Problem Solver") they were developing. This tradition, centered at Carnegie Mellon University would eventually culminate in the development of the Soar architecture in the middle 80s.[81][82]
- Logic based
- Unlike Newell and Simon, John McCarthy felt that machines did not need to simulate human thought, but should instead try to find the essence of abstract reasoning and problem solving, regardless of whether people used the same algorithms.[77] His laboratory at Stanford (SAIL) focused on using formal logic to solve a wide variety of problems, including knowledge representation, planning and learning.[83] Logic was also focus of the work at the University of Edinburgh and elsewhere in Europe which led to the development of the programming language Prolog and the science of logic programming.[84]
- "Anti-logic" or "scruffy"
- Researchers at MIT (such as Marvin Minsky and Seymour Papert)[85] found that solving difficult problems in vision and natural language processing required ad-hoc solutions – they argued that there was no simple and general principle (like logic) that would capture all the aspects of intelligent behavior. Roger Schank described their "anti-logic" approaches as "scruffy" (as opposed to the "neat" paradigms at CMU and Stanford).[78] Commonsense knowledge bases (such as Doug Lenat's Cyc) are an example of "scruffy" AI, since they must be built by hand, one complicated concept at a time.[86]
- Knowledge based
- When computers with large memories became available around 1970, researchers from all three traditions began to build knowledge into AI applications.[87] This "knowledge revolution" led to the development and deployment of expert systems (introduced by Edward Feigenbaum), the first truly successful form of AI software.[35] The knowledge revolution was also driven by the realization that enormous amounts of knowledge would be required by many simple AI applications.
Sub-symbolic
During the 1960s, symbolic approaches had achieved great success at simulating high-level thinking in small demonstration programs. Approaches based on cybernetics or neural networks were abandoned or pushed into the background.[88] By the 1980s, however, progress in symbolic AI seemed to stall and many believed that symbolic systems would never be able to imitate all the processes of human cognition, especially perception, robotics, learning and pattern recognition. A number of researchers began to look into "sub-symbolic" approaches to specific AI problems.[79]
- Bottom-up, embodied, situated, behavior-based or nouvelle AI
- Researchers from the related field of robotics, such as Rodney Brooks, rejected symbolic AI and focused on the basic engineering problems that would allow robots to move and survive.[89] Their work revived the non-symbolic viewpoint of the early cybernetics researchers of the 50s and reintroduced the use of control theory in AI. These approaches are also conceptually related to the embodied mind thesis.
- Computational Intelligence
- Interest in neural networks and "connectionism" was revived by David Rumelhart and others in the middle 1980s.[90] These and other sub-symbolic approaches, such as fuzzy systems and evolutionary computation, are now studied collectively by the emerging discipline of computational intelligence.[91]
Statistical
In the 1990s, AI researchers developed sophisticated mathematical tools to solve specific subproblems. These tools are truly scientific, in the sense that their results are both measurable and verifiable, and they have been responsible for many of AI's recent successes. The shared mathematical language has also permitted a high level of collaboration with more established fields (like mathematics, economics or operations research). Stuart Russell and Peter Norvig describe this movement as nothing less than a "revolution" and "the victory of the neats."[38]
Integrating the approaches
- Intelligent agent paradigm
- An intelligent agent is a system that perceives its environment and takes actions which maximizes its chances of success. The simplest intelligent agents are programs that solve specific problems. The most complicated intelligent agents are rational, thinking humans.[92] The paradigm gives researchers license to study isolated problems and find solutions that are both verifiable and useful, without agreeing on one single approach. An agent that solves a specific problem can use any approach that works — some agents are symbolic and logical, some are sub-symbolic neural networks and others may use new approaches. The paradigm also gives researchers a common language to communicate with other fields—such as decision theory and economics—that also use concepts of abstract agents. The intelligent agent paradigm became widely accepted during the 1990s.[93]
- Agent architectures and cognitive architectures
- Researchers have designed systems to build intelligent systems out of interacting intelligent agents in a multi-agent system.[94] A system with both symbolic and sub-symbolic components is a hybrid intelligent system, and the study of such systems is artificial intelligence systems integration. A hierarchical control system provides a bridge between sub-symbolic AI at its lowest, reactive levels and traditional symbolic AI at its highest levels, where relaxed time constraints permit planning and world modelling.[95] Rodney Brooks' subsumption architecture was an early proposal for such a hierarchical system.
Tools
In the course of 50 years of research, AI has developed a large number of tools to solve the most difficult problems in computer science. A few of the most general of these methods are discussed below.
Search and optimization
Many problems in AI can be solved in theory by intelligently searching through many possible solutions:[96] Reasoning can be reduced to performing a search. For example, logical proof can be viewed as searching for a path that leads from premises to conclusions, where each step is the application of an inference rule.[97] Planning algorithms search through trees of goals and subgoals, attempting to find a path to a target goal, a process called means-ends analysis.[98] Robotics algorithms for moving limbs and grasping objects use local searches in configuration space.[67] Many learning algorithms use search algorithms based on optimization.
Simple exhaustive searches[99] are rarely sufficient for most real world problems: the search space (the number of places to search) quickly grows to astronomical numbers. The result is a search that is too slow or never completes. The solution, for many problems, is to use "heuristics" or "rules of thumb" that eliminate choices that are unlikely to lead to the goal (called "pruning the search tree"). Heuristics supply the program with a "best guess" for what path the solution lies on.[100]
A very different kind of search came to prominence in the 1990s, based on the mathematical theory of optimization. For many problems, it is possible to begin the search with some form of a guess and then refine the guess incrementally until no more refinements can be made. These algorithms can be visualized as blind hill climbing: we begin the search at a random point on the landscape, and then, by jumps or steps, we keep moving our guess uphill, until we reach the top. Other optimization algorithms are simulated annealing, beam search and random optimization.[101]
Evolutionary computation uses a form of optimization search. For example, they may begin with a population of organisms (the guesses) and then allow them to mutate and recombine, selecting only the fittest to survive each generation (refining the guesses). Forms of evolutionary computation include swarm intelligence algorithms (such as ant colony or particle swarm optimization)[102] and evolutionary algorithms (such as genetic algorithms[103] and genetic programming[104][105]).
Logic
Logic[106] was introduced into AI research by John McCarthy in his 1958 Advice Taker proposal. Logic is used for knowledge representation and problem solving, but it can be applied to other problems as well. For example, the satplan algorithm uses logic for planning[107] and inductive logic programming is a method for learning.[108]
Several different forms of logic are used in AI research. Propositional or sentential logic[109] is the logic of statements which can be true or false. First-order logic[110] also allows the use of quantifiers and predicates, and can express facts about objects, their properties, and their relations with each other. Fuzzy logic,[111] is a version of first-order logic which allows the truth of a statement to be represented as a value between 0 and 1, rather than simply True (1) or False (0). Fuzzy systems can be used for uncertain reasoning and have been widely used in modern industrial and consumer product control systems. Default logics, non-monotonic logics and circumscription[51] are forms of logic designed to help with default reasoning and the qualification problem. Several extensions of logic have been designed to handle specific domains of knowledge, such as: description logics;[45] situation calculus, event calculus and fluent calculus (for representing events and time);[46] causal calculus;[47] belief calculus; and modal logics.[48]
In 1963, J. Alan Robinson discovered a simple, complete and entirely algorithmic method for logical deduction which can easily be performed by digital computers.[112] However, a naive implementation of the algorithm quickly leads to a combinatorial explosion or an infinite loop. In 1974, Robert Kowalski suggested representing logical expressions as Horn clauses (statements in the form of rules: "if p then q"), which reduced logical deduction to backward chaining or forward chaining. This greatly alleviated (but did not eliminate) the problem.[97][113]
Probabilistic methods for uncertain reasoning
Many problems in AI (in reasoning, planning, learning, perception and robotics) require the agent to operate with incomplete or uncertain information. Starting in the late 80s and early 90s, Judea Pearl and others championed the use of methods drawn from probability theory and economics to devise a number of powerful tools to solve these problems.[114][115]
Bayesian networks[116] are a very general tool that can be used for a large number of problems: reasoning (using the Bayesian inference algorithm),[117] learning (using the expectation-maximization algorithm),[118] planning (using decision networks)[119] and perception (using dynamic Bayesian networks).[120] Probabilistic algorithms can also be used for filtering, prediction, smoothing and finding explanations for streams of data, helping perception systems to analyze processes that occur over time[121] (e.g., hidden Markov models[122] or Kalman filters[123]).
A key concept from the science of economics is "utility": a measure of how valuable something is to an intelligent agent. Precise mathematical tools have been developed that analyze how an agent can make choices and plan, using decision theory, decision analysis,[124] information value theory.[57] These tools include models such as Markov decision processes,[125] dynamic decision networks,[125] game theory and mechanism design.[126]
Classifiers and statistical learning methods
The simplest AI applications can be divided into two types: classifiers ("if shiny then diamond") and controllers ("if shiny then pick up"). Controllers do however also classify conditions before inferring actions, and therefore classification forms a central part of many AI systems. Classifiers are functions that use pattern matching to determine a closest match. They can be tuned according to examples, making them very attractive for use in AI. These examples are known as observations or patterns. In supervised learning, each pattern belongs to a certain predefined class. A class can be seen as a decision that has to be made. All the observations combined with their class labels are known as a data set. When a new observation is received, that observation is classified based on previous experience.[127]
A classifier can be trained in various ways; there are many statistical and machine learning approaches. The most widely used classifiers are the neural network,[128] kernel methods such as the support vector machine,[129] k-nearest neighbor algorithm,[130] Gaussian mixture model,[131] naive Bayes classifier,[132] and decision tree.[133] The performance of these classifiers have been compared over a wide range of tasks. Classifier performance depends greatly on the characteristics of the data to be classified. There is no single classifier that works best on all given problems; this is also referred to as the "no free lunch" theorem. Determining a suitable classifier for a given problem is still more an art than science.[134]
Neural networks
The study of artificial neural networks[128] began in the decade before the field AI research was founded, in the work of Walter Pitts and Warren McCullough. Other important early researchers were Frank Rosenblatt, who invented the perceptron and Paul Werbos who developed the backpropagation algorithm.[135]
The main categories of networks are acyclic or feedforward neural networks (where the signal passes in only one direction) and recurrent neural networks (which allow feedback). Among the most popular feedforward networks are perceptrons, multi-layer perceptrons and radial basis networks.[136] Among recurrent networks, the most famous is the Hopfield net, a form of attractor network, which was first described by John Hopfield in 1982.[137] Neural networks can be applied to the problem of intelligent control (for robotics) or learning, using such techniques as Hebbian learning and competitive learning.[138]
Jeff Hawkins argues that research in neural networks has stalled because it has failed to model the essential properties of the neocortex, and has suggested a model (Hierarchical Temporal Memory) that is based on neurological research.[139]
Control theory
Control theory, the grandchild of cybernetics, has many important applications, especially in robotics.[140]
Languages
AI researchers have developed several specialized languages for AI research, including Lisp[141] and Prolog.[142]
Evaluating progress
How can one determine if an agent is intelligent? In 1950, Alan Turing proposed a general procedure to test the intelligence of an agent now known as the Turing test. This procedure allows almost all the major problems of artificial intelligence to be tested. However, it is a very difficult challenge and at present all agents fail.
Artificial intelligence can also be evaluated on specific problems such as small problems in chemistry, hand-writing recognition and game-playing. Such tests have been termed subject matter expert Turing tests. Smaller problems provide more achievable goals and there are an ever-increasing number of positive results.
The broad classes of outcome for an AI test are:
- Optimal: it is not possible to perform better
- Strong super-human: performs better than all humans
- Super-human: performs better than most humans
- Sub-human: performs worse than most humans
For example, performance at draughts is optimal,[143] performance at chess is super-human and nearing strong super-human,[144] and performance at many everyday tasks performed by humans is sub-human.
A quite different approach measures machine intelligence through tests which are developed from mathematical definitions of intelligence. Examples of these kinds of tests start in the late nineties devising intelligence tests using notions from Kolmogorov Complexity and data compression [145] [146]. Similar definitions of machine intelligence have been put forward by Marcus Hutter in his book Universal Artificial Intelligence (Springer 2005), an idea further developed by Legg and Hutter [147]. Two major advantages of mathematical definitions are their applicability to nonhuman intelligences and their absence of a requirement for human testers.
Applications
此章节需要扩充。 (2009年7月1日) |
Artificial intelligence has successfully been used in a wide range of fields including medical diagnosis, stock trading, robot control, law, scientific discovery, video games, toys, and Web search engines. Frequently, when a technique reaches mainstream use, it is no longer considered artificial intelligence, sometimes described as the AI effect.[148] It may also become integrated into artificial life.
Competitions and prizes
There are a number of competitions and prizes to promote research in artificial intelligence. The main areas promoted are: general machine intelligence, conversational behavior, data-mining, driverless cars, robot soccer and games.
Platforms
A platform (or "computing platform")is defined by Wikipedia as "some sort of hardware architecture or software framework (including application frameworks), that allows software to run." As Rodney Brooks [149]pointed out many years ago, it is not just the artificial intelligence software that defines the AI features of the platform, but rather the actual platform itself that affects the AI that results, ie, we need to be working out AI problems on real world platforms rather than in isolation.
A wide variety of platforms has allowed different aspects of AI to develop, ranging from expert systems, albeit PC-based but still an entire real-world system to various robot platforms such as the widely available Roomba with open interface [150].
Philosophy
Artificial intelligence, by claiming to be able to recreate the capabilities of the human mind, is both a challenge and an inspiration for philosophy. Are there limits to how intelligent machines can be? Is there an essential difference between human intelligence and artificial intelligence? Can a machine have a mind and consciousness? A few of the most influential answers to these questions are given below.[151]
- Turing's "polite convention"
- If a machine acts as intelligently as a human being, then it is as intelligent as a human being. Alan Turing theorized that, ultimately, we can only judge the intelligence of a machine based on its behavior. This theory forms the basis of the Turing test.[152]
- The Dartmouth proposal
- "Every aspect of learning or any other feature of intelligence can be so precisely described that a machine can be made to simulate it." This assertion was printed in the proposal for the Dartmouth Conference of 1956, and represents the position of most working AI researchers.[153]
- Newell and Simon's physical symbol system hypothesis
- "A physical symbol system has the necessary and sufficient means of general intelligent action." Newell and Simon argue that intelligences consists of formal operations on symbols.[154] Hubert Dreyfus argued that, on the contrary, human expertise depends on unconscious instinct rather than conscious symbol manipulation and on having a "feel" for the situation rather than explicit symbolic knowledge. (See Dreyfus' critique of AI.)[155][156]
- Gödel's incompleteness theorem
- A formal system (such as a computer program) can not prove all true statements. Roger Penrose is among those who claim that Gödel's theorem limits what machines can do. (See The Emperor's New Mind.)[157][158]
- Searle's strong AI hypothesis
- "The appropriately programmed computer with the right inputs and outputs would thereby have a mind in exactly the same sense human beings have minds."[159] Searle counters this assertion with his Chinese room argument, which asks us to look inside the computer and try to find where the "mind" might be.[160]
- The artificial brain argument
- The brain can be simulated. Hans Moravec, Ray Kurzweil and others have argued that it is technologically feasible to copy the brain directly into hardware and software, and that such a simulation will be essentially identical to the original.[161]
Speculation and fiction
AI is a common topic in both science fiction and in projections about the future of technology and society. The existence of an artificial intelligence that rivals human intelligence raises difficult ethical issues and the potential power of the technology inspires both hopes and fears.
Mary Shelley's Frankenstein[162] considers a key issue in the ethics of artificial intelligence: if a machine can be created that has intelligence, could it also feel? If it can feel, does it have the same rights as a human? The idea also appears in modern science fiction: the film Artificial Intelligence: A.I. considers a machine in the form of a small boy which has been given the ability to feel human emotions, including, tragically, the capacity to suffer. This issue, now known as "robot rights", is currently being considered by, for example, California's Institute for the Future,[163] although many critics believe that the discussion is premature.[164]
Another issue explored by both science fiction writers and futurists is the impact of artificial intelligence on society. In fiction, AI has appeared as a servant (R2D2 in Star Wars), a law enforcer (K.I.T.T. "Knight Rider"), a comrade (Lt. Commander Data in Star Trek), a conqueror (The Matrix), a dictator (With Folded Hands), an exterminator (Terminator, Battlestar Galactica), an extension to human abilities (Ghost in the Shell) and the saviour of the human race (R. Daneel Olivaw in the Foundation Series). Academic sources have considered such consequences as: a decreased demand for human labor,[165] the enhancement of human ability or experience,[166] and a need for redefinition of human identity and basic values.[167]
Several futurists argue that artificial intelligence will transcend the limits of progress and fundamentally transform humanity. Ray Kurzweil has used Moore's law (which describes the relentless exponential improvement in digital technology with uncanny accuracy) to calculate that desktop computers will have the same processing power as human brains by the year 2029, and that by 2045 artificial intelligence will reach a point where it is able to improve itself at a rate that far exceeds anything conceivable in the past, a scenario that science fiction writer Vernor Vinge named the "technological singularity".[166] Edward Fredkin argues that "artificial intelligence is the next stage in evolution,"[168] an idea first proposed by Samuel Butler's "Darwin among the Machines" (1863), and expanded upon by George Dyson in his book of the same name in 1998. Several futurists and science fiction writers have predicted that humans and machines will merge in the future into cyborgs that are more capable and powerful than either. This idea, called transhumanism, which has roots in Aldous Huxley and Robert Ettinger, is now associated with robot designer Hans Moravec, cyberneticist Kevin Warwick and inventor Ray Kurzweil.[166] Transhumanism has been illustrated in fiction as well, for example in the manga Ghost in the Shell and the science fiction series Dune. Pamela McCorduck writes that these scenarios are expressions of the ancient human desire to, as she calls it, "forge the gods."[6]
See also
- Artificial Intelligence (journal)
- List of scientific journals
- List of AI projects
- List of AI researchers
- List of emerging technologies
- List of basic artificial intelligence topics
- List of important AI publications
- Technological singularity
- Philosophy of mind
- Psychometric artificial intelligence
- Cognitive sciences
Notes
- ^ Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,p. 1 (who use the term "computational intelligence" as a synonym for artificial intelligence). Other textbooks that define AI this way include Nilsson (1998), and Russell & Norvig (2003) (who prefer the term "rational agent") and write "The whole-agent view is now widely accepted in the field" (Russell & Norvig 2003,第55页)
- ^ This definition, in terms of goals, actions, perception and environment, is due to Russell & Norvig (2003) . Other definitions also include knowledge and learning as additional criteria.
- ^ Although there is some controversy on this point (see Crevier 1993,第50页 ), McCarthy states unequivocally "I came up with the term" in a c|net interview. (See Getting Machines to Think Like Us.)
- ^ See John McCarthy, What is Artificial Intelligence?
- ^ See the Dartmouth proposal, under Philosophy, below.
- ^ 6.0 6.1 6.2 This is a central idea of Pamela McCorduck's Machines That Think. She writes: "I like to think of artificial intelligence as the scientific apotheosis of a venerable cultural tradition." (McCorduck 2004,第34页) "Artificial intelligence in one form or another is an idea that has pervaded Western intellectual history, a dream in urgent need of being realized." (McCorduck 2004,第xviii页) "Our history is full of attempts—nutty, eerie, comical, earnest, legendary and real—to make artificial intelligences, to reproduce what is the essential us—bypassing the ordinary means. Back and forth between myth and reality, our imaginations supplying what our workshops couldn't, we have engaged for a long time in this odd form of self-reproduction." (McCorduck 2004,第3页) She traces the desire back to its Hellenistic roots and calls it the urge to "forge the Gods." (McCorduck 2004,第340-400页)
- ^ The optimism referred to includes the predictions of early AI researchers (see optimism in the history of AI) as well as the ideas of modern transhumanists such as Ray Kurzweil.
- ^ The "setbacks" referred to include the ALPAC report of 1966, the abandonment of perceptrons in 1970, the the Lighthill Report of 1973 and the collapse of the lisp machine market in 1987.
- ^ 9.0 9.1
AI applications widely used behind the scenes:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第28页
- Kurzweil 2005,第265页
- NRC 1999,第216-222页
- ^ Pamela McCorduck (2004,第424页) writes of "the rough shattering of AI in subfields—vision, natural language, decision theory, genetic algorithms, robotics ... and these with own sub-subfield—that would hardly have anything to say to each other."
- ^ 11.0 11.1 This list of intelligent traits is based on the topics covered by the major AI textbooks, including:
- ^ 12.0 12.1 General intelligence (strong AI) is discussed in popular introductions to AI:
- ^
AI in Myth:
- McCorduck 2004,第4-5页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第939页
- ^
Sacred statues as artificial intelligence:
- Crevier (1993,第1页) (statue of Amun)
- McCorduck (2004,第6-9页)
- ^ Needham 1986,第53页
- ^ McCorduck 2004,第6页
- ^ A Thirteenth Century Programmable Robot. Shef.ac.uk. [2009-04-25].
- ^ McCorduck 2004,第17页
- ^ Takwin: O'Connor, Kathleen Malone. The alchemical creation of life (takwin) and other concepts of Genesis in medieval Islam. University of Pennsylvania. 1994 [2007-01-10].
- ^ Golem: McCorduck 2004,第15-16页 , Buchanan 2005,第50页
- ^ McCorduck 2004,第13-14页
- ^ McCorduck 2004,第17-25页
- ^ This insight, that digital computers can simulate any process of formal reasoning, is known as the Church-Turing thesis.
- ^ 24.0 24.1
AI's immediate precursors:
- McCorduck 2004,第51-107页
- Crevier 1993,第27-32页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第15, 940页
- Moravec 1988,第3页
- ^
Dartmouth conference:
- McCorduck 2004,第111-136页
- Crevier 1993,第47-49页 , who writes "the conference is generally recognized as the official birthdate of the new science."
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第17页 , who call the conference "the birth of artifcial intelligence."
- NRC 1999,第200-201页
- ^
Hegemony of the Dartmouth conference attendees:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第17页 , who write "for the next 20 years the field would be dominated by these people and their students."
- McCorduck 2004,第129-130页
- ^ Russell and Norvig write "it was astonishing whenever a computer did anything kind of smartish." Russell & Norvig 2003,第18页
- ^
"Golden years" of AI (successful symbolic reasoning programs 1956-1973):
- McCorduck,第243-252页
- Crevier 1993,第52-107页
- Moravec 1988,第9页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第18-21页
- ^
DARPA pours money into undirected pure research into AI during the 1960s:
- McCorduck 2005,第131页
- Crevier 1993,第51, 64-65页
- NRC 1999,第204-205页
- ^
- ^ Simon 1965,第96页 quoted in Crevier 1993,第109页
- ^ Minsky 1967,第2页 quoted in Crevier 1993,第109页 .
- ^ See Template:See section.
- ^
First AI Winter, Mansfield Amendment, Lighthill report
- Crevier 1993,第115-117页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第22页
- NRC 1999,第212-213页
- Howe 1994
- ^ 35.0 35.1
Expert systems:
- ACM 1998,I.2.1,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第22−24页
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第227-331页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 17.4
- McCorduck 2004,第327-335, 434-435页
- Crevier 1993,第145-62, 197−203页
- ^
Boom of the 1980s: rise of expert systems, Fifth Generation Project, Alvey, MCC, SCI:
- McCorduck 2004,第426-441页
- Crevier 1993,第161-162,197-203, 211, 240页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第24页
- NRC 1999,第210-211页
- ^
Second AI Winter:
- McCorduck 2004,第430-435页
- Crevier 1993,第209-210页
- NRC 1999,第214-216页
- ^ 38.0 38.1
Formal methods are now preferred ("Victory of the neats"):
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第25-26页
- McCorduck 2004,第486-487页
- ^
Problem solving, puzzle solving, game playing and deduction:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,chpt. 3-9 ,
- Poole et al.,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,chpt. 3,4,6,8,
- Nilsson,chpt. 7-12
- ^
Uncertain reasoning:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第452-644页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第345-395页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第333-381页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 19
- ^
Intractability and efficiency and the combinatorial explosion:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第9, 21-22页
- ^
Cognitive science has provided several famous examples:
- Wason (1966) showed that people do poorly on completely abstract problems, but if the problem is restated to allow the use of intuitive social intelligence, performance dramatically improves. (See Wason selection task)
- Tversky, Slovic & Kahnemann (1982) have shown that people are terrible at elementary problems that involve uncertain reasoning. (See list of cognitive biases for several examples).
- Lakoff & Núñez (2000) have controversially argued that even our skills at mathematics depend on knowledge and skills that come from "the body", i.e. sensorimotor and perceptual skills. (See Where Mathematics Comes From)
- ^
Knowledge representation:
- ACM 1998,I.2.4,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第320-363页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第23-46, 69-81, 169-196, 235-277, 281-298, 319-345页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第227-243页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 18
- ^
Knowledge engineering:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第260-266页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第199-233页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. ~17.1-17.4
- ^ 45.0 45.1
Representing categories and relations: Semantic networks, description logics, inheritance (including frames and scripts):
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第349-354页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第174-177页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第248-258页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 18.3
- ^ 46.0 46.1
Representing events and time:Situation calculus, event calculus, fluent calculus (including solving the frame problem):
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第328-341页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第281-298页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 18.2
- ^ 47.0 47.1
Causal calculus:
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第335-337页
- ^ 48.0 48.1
Representing knowledge about knowledge: Belief calculus, modal logics:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第341-344页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第275-277页
- ^
Ontology:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第320-328页
- ^ McCarthy & Hayes 1969. While McCarthy was primarily concerned with issues in the logical representation of actions, Russell & Norvig 2003 apply the term to the more general issue of default reasoning in the vast network of assumptions underlying all our commonsense knowledge.
- ^ 51.0 51.1
Default reasoning and default logic, non-monotonic logics, circumscription, closed world assumption, abduction (Poole et al. places abduction under "default reasoning". Luger et al. places this under "uncertain reasoning"):
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第354-360页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第248-256, 323-335页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第335-363页,
- Nilsson 1998,~18.3.3
- ^
Breadth of commonsense knowledge:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第21页 ,
- Crevier 1993,第113-114页 ,
- Moravec 1988,第13页,
- Lenat & Guha 1989 (Introduction)
- ^ Dreyfus & Dreyfus 1986
- ^ Gladwell 2005
- ^ 55.0 55.1
Expert knowledge as embodied intuition:
- Dreyfus & Dreyfus 1986 (Hubert Dreyfus is a philosopher and critic of AI who was among the first to argue that most useful human knowledge was encoded sub-symbolically. See Dreyfus' critique of AI)
- Gladwell 2005 (Gladwell's Blink is a popular introduction to sub-symbolic reasoning and knowledge.)
- Hawkins 2005 (Hawkins argues that sub-symbolic knowledge should be the primary focus of AI research.)
- ^
Planning:
- ACM 1998,~I.2.8,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第375-459页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第281-316页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第314-329页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 10.1-2, 22
- ^ 57.0 57.1
Information value theory:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第600-604页
- ^
Classical planning:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第375-430页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第281-315页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第314-329页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 10.1-2, 22
- ^
Planning and acting in non-deterministic domains: conditional planning, execution monitoring, replanning and continuous planning:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第430-449页
- ^
Multi-agent planning and emergent behavior:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第449-455页
- ^
Learning:
- ACM 1998,I.2.6,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第649-788页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第397-438页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第385-542页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 3.3 , 10.3, 17.5, 20
- ^ Alan Turing discussed the centrality of learning as early as 1950, in his classic paper Computing Machinery and Intelligence. (Turing 1950)
- ^
Reinforcement learning:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第763-788页
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第442-449页
- ^
Natural language processing:
- ACM 1998,I.2.7
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第790-831页
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第91-104页
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第591-632页
- ^
Applications of natural language processing, including information retrieval (i.e. text mining) and machine translation:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第840-857页 ,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第623-630页
- ^
Robotics:
- ACM 1998,I.2.9,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第901-942页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第443-460页
- ^ 67.0 67.1
Moving and configuration space:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第916-932页
- ^
Robotic mapping (localization, etc):
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第908-915页
- ^
Machine perception:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第537-581, 863-898页
- Nilsson 1998,~chpt. 6
- ^
Computer vision:
- ACM 1998,I.2.10
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第863-898页
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 6
- ^
Speech recognition:
- ACM 1998,~I.2.7
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第568-578页
- ^
Object recognition:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第885-892页
- ^ Emotion and affective computing:
- ^ Gerald Edelman, Igor Aleksander and others have both argued that artificial consciousness is required for strong AI. (Aleksander 1995) (Edelman 2007) Ray Kurzweil, Jeff Hawkins and others have argued that strong AI requires a simulation of the operation of the human brain. (Hawkins & Blakeslee 2004) (Kurzweil 2005)
- ^ AI complete: Shapiro 1992,第9页
- ^ Nils Nilsson writes: "Simply put, there is wide disagreement in the field about what AI is all about." (Nilsson 1983,第10页)
- ^ 77.0 77.1
Biological intelligence vs. intelligence in general:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第2-3页 , who make the analogy with aeronautical engineering.
- McCorduck 2004,第100-101页 , who writes that there are "two major branches of artifical intelligence: one aimed at producing intelligent behavior regardless of how it was accomplioshed, and the other aimed at modeling intelligent processes found in nature, particularly human ones."
- Kolata 1982, a paper in Science, which describes McCathy's indifference to biological models. Kolata quotes McCarthy as writing: "This is AI, so we don't care if it's psychologically real"[1]. McCarthy recently reiterated his position at the AI@50 conference where he said "Artificial intelligence is not, by definition, simulation of human intelligence" (Maker 2006).
- ^ 78.0 78.1
Neats vs. scruffies:
- McCorduck 2004,第421-424, 486-489页
- Crevier 1993,第168页
- Nilsson 1983,第10-11页
- ^ 79.0 79.1
Symbolic vs. sub-symbolic AI:
- Nilsson (1998,第7页), who uses the term "sub-symbolic".
- ^ Haugeland 1985,第112-117页
- ^
Cognitive simulation, Newell and Simon, AI at CMU (then called Carnegie Tech):
- McCorduck 2004,第139-179, 245-250, 322-323 (EPAM)页
- Crevier 2004,第145-149页
- ^
Soar (history):
- McCorduck 2004,第450-451页
- Crevier 1993,第258-263页
- ^
McCarthy and AI research at SAIL and SRI:
- McCorduck 2004,第251-259页
- Crevier 1993,第Check页
- ^
AI research at Edinburgh and in France, birth of Prolog:
- Crevier 1993,第193-196页
- Howe 1994
- ^
AI at MIT under Marvin Minsky in the 1960s :
- McCorduck 2004,第259-305页
- Crevier 1993,第83-102, 163-176页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第19页
- ^
Cyc:
- McCorduck 2004,第489页 , who calls it "a determinedly scruffy enterprise"
- Crevier 1993,第239−243页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第363−365页
- Lenat & Guha 1989
- ^
Knowledge revolution:
- McCorduck 2004,第266-276, 298-300, 314, 421页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第22-23页
- ^ The most dramatic case of sub-symbolic AI being pushed into the background was the devastating critique of perceptrons by Marvin Minsky and Seymour Papert in 1969. See History of AI, AI winter, or Frank Rosenblatt.
- ^
Embodied approaches to AI:
- McCorduck 2004,第454-462页
- Brooks 1990
- Moravec 1988
- ^
Revival of connectionism:
- Crevier 1993,第214-215页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第25页
- ^ See IEEE Computational Intelligence Society
- ^
The intelligent agent paradigm:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第27, 32-58, 968-972页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第7-21页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第235-240页
- ^ "The whole-agent view is now widely accepted in the field" Russell & Norvig 2003,第55页
- ^
Agent architectures, hybrid intelligent systems:
- Russell & Norvig (1998,第27, 932, 970-972页)
- Nilsson (1998,chpt. 25)
- ^ Albus, J. S. 4-D/RCS reference model architecture for unmanned ground vehicles. In G Gerhart, R Gunderson, and C Shoemaker, editors, Proceedings of the SPIE AeroSense Session on Unmanned Ground Vehicle Technology, volume 3693, pages 11—20
- ^
Search algorithms:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第59-189页
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第113-163页
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第79-164, 193-219页
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 7-12
- ^ 97.0 97.1
Forward chaining, backward chaining, Horn clauses, and logical deduction as search:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第217-225, 280-294页
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第~46-52页
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第62-73页
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 4.2, 7.2
- ^
State space search and planning:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第382-387页
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第298-305页
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 10.1-2
- ^
Uninformed searches (breadth first search, depth first search and general state space search):
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第59-93页
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第113-132页
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第79-121页
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 8
- ^
Heuristic or informed searches (e.g., greedy best first and A*):
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第94-109页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第pp. 132-147页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第133-150页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 9
- ^
Optimization searches:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第110-116,120-129页
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第56-163页
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第127-133页
- ^
Artificial life and society based learning:
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第530-541页
- ^
Genetic algorithms for learning:
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第509-530页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 4.2.
- ^
Koza, John R. Genetic Programming. MIT Press. 1992. ISBN 0262111705. 已忽略未知参数
|subtitle=
(帮助) - ^ Poli, R., Langdon, W. B., McPhee, N. F. A Field Guide to Genetic Programming. Lulu.com, freely available from http://www.gp-field-guide.org.uk/. 2008. ISBN 978-1-4092-0073-4.
- ^
Logic:
- ACM 1998,~I.2.3,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第194-310页 ,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第35-77页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 13-16
- ^
Satplan:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第402-407页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第300-301页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 21
- ^
Explanation based learning, relevance based learning, inductive logic programming, case based reasoning:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第678-710页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第414-416页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第~422-442页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 10.3, 17.5
- ^
Propositional logic:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第204-233页 ,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第45-50页
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 13
- ^
First-order logic and features such as equality:
- ACM 1998,~I.2.4,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第240-310页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第268-275页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第50-62页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 15
- ^
Fuzzy logic:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第526-527页
- ^
Resolution and unification:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第213-217, 275-280, 295-306页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第56-58页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第554-575页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 14 & 16
- ^
History of logic programming:
- Crevier 1993,第190-196页 .
- Howe 1994
- McCorduck 2004,第51页 ,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第19页
- ^
Judea Pearl's contribution to AI:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第25-26页
- ^
Stochastic methods for uncertain reasoning:
- ACM 1998,~I.2.3,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第462-644页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第345-395页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第165-191, 333-381页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 19
- ^
Bayesian networks:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第492-523页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第361-381页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第~182-190, ~363-379页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 19.3-4
- ^
Bayesian inference algorithm:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第504-519页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第361-381页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第~363-379页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 19.4 & 7
- ^
Bayesian learning and the expectation-maximization algorithm:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第712-724页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第424-433页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 20
- ^
Bayesian decision networks:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第597-600页
- ^
Dynamic Bayesian network:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第551-557页
- ^ Stochastic temporal models: Russell & Norvig 2003,第537-581页
- ^
Hidden Markov model:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第549-551页
- ^
Kalman filter:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第551-557页
- ^
decision theory and decision analysis:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第584-597页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第381-394页
- ^ 125.0 125.1
Markov decision processes and dynamic decision networks:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第613-631页
- ^
Game theory and mechanism design:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第631-643页
- ^
Statistical learning methods and classifiers:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第712-754页 ,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第453-541页
- ^ 128.0 128.1
Neural networks and connectionism:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第736-748页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第408-414页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第453-505页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 3
- ^
Kernel methods:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第749-752页
- ^
K-nearest neighbor algorithm:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第733-736页
- ^
Gaussian mixture model:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第725-727页
- ^
Naive Bayes classifier:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第718页
- ^
Decision tree:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第653-664页 ,
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第403-408页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第408-417页
- ^ van der Walt 2006
- ^
Backpropagation:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第744-748页 ,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第467-474页,
- Nilsson 1998,chpt. 3.3
- ^
Feedforward networks, perceptrons radial basis networks:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第739-748, 758页
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第458-467页
- ^
Recurrent networks, Hopfield nets:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第758页
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第474-505页
- ^
Competitive learning, Hebbian coincidence learning, Hopfield networks and attractor networks:
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第474-505页
- ^ Hawkins & Blakeslee 2004
- ^
Control theory:
- ACM 1998,~I.2.8,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第926-932页
- ^
Lisp:
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第723-821页
- Crevier 1993,第59-62页 ,
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第18页
- ^
Prolog:
- Poole, Mackworth & Goebel 1998,第477-491页,
- Luger & Stubblefield 2004,第641-676, 575-581页
- ^ Schaeffer, Jonathan. Checkers Is Solved. Science. 2007-07-19 [2007-07-20].
- ^ Computer Chess#Computers versus humans
- ^ Jose Hernandez-Orallo. Beyond the Turing Test. Journal of Logic, Language and Information. 2000, 9 (4): 447–466 [2009-07-21]. doi:10.1023/A:1008367325700.
- ^ D L Dowe and A R Hajek. A computational extension to the Turing Test. Proceedings of the 4th Conference of the Australasian Cognitive Science Society. 1997 [2009-07-21].
- ^ Shane Legg and Marcus Hutter. Universal Intelligence: A Definition of Machine Intelligence (pdf). Minds and Machines. 2007, 17: 391–444 [2009-07-21]. doi:10.1007/s11023-007-9079-x.
- ^ AI set to exceed human brain power (web article). CNN.com. 2006-07-26 [2008-02-26].
- ^ Brooks, R.A., "How to build complete creatures rather than isolated cognitive simulators," in K. VanLehn (ed.), Architectures for Intelligence, pp. 225-239, Lawrence Erlbaum Assosiates, Hillsdale, NJ, 1991.
- ^ http://hackingroomba.com/?s=atmel
- ^
All of these positions below are mentioned in standard discussions of the subject, such as:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第947-960页
- Fearn 2007,第38-55页
- ^
Philosophical implications of the Turing test:
- Turing 1950
- Haugeland 1985,第6-9页
- Crevier 1993,第24页
- McCorduck 2004,第70–71页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第2-3 and 948页
- ^ Dartmouth proposal:
- ^
The physical symbol systems hypothesis:
- Newell & Simon 1976,第116页
- McCorduck 2004,第153页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第18页
- ^ Dreyfus criticized the necessary condition of the physical symbol system hypothesis, which he called the "psychological assumption": "The mind can be viewed as a device operating on bits of information according to formal rules". (Dreyfus 1992,第156页)
- ^
Dreyfus' critique of artificial intelligence:
- Dreyfus 1972, Dreyfus & Dreyfus 1986
- Crevier 1993,第120–132页
- McCorduck 2004,第211–239页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第950–952页 ,
- ^ This is a paraphrase of the important implication of Gödel's theorems.
- ^
The Mathematical Objection:
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第949页
- McCorduck 2004,第448–449页
- Turing 1950 under “(2) The Mathematical Objection”
- Hofstadter 1979,
- ^ This version is from Searle (1999), and is also quoted in Dennett 1991,第435页. Searle's original formulation was "The appropriately programmed computer really is a mind, in the sense that computers given the right programs can be literally said to understand and have other cognitive states." (Searle 1980,第1页). Strong AI is defined similarly by Russell & Norvig (2003,第947页) : "The assertion that machines could possibly act intelligently (or, perhaps better, act as if they were intelligent) is called the 'weak AI' hypothesis by philosophers, and the assertion that machines that do so are actually thinking (as opposed to simulating thinking) is called the 'strong AI' hypothesis."
- ^
Searle's Chinese Room argument:
- Searle 1980, Searle 1991
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第958-960页
- McCorduck 2004,第443-445页
- Crevier 1993,第269-271页
- ^
Artificial brain:
- Moravec 1988
- Kurzweil 2005,第262页
- Russell & Norvig,第957页
- Crevier 1993,第271 and 279页
- ^ McCorduck (2004,第190-25页) discusses Frankenstein and identifies the key ethical issues as scientific hubris and the suffering of the monster, i.e. robot rights.
- ^ Robot rights:
- ^ See the Times Online, Human rights for robots? We’re getting carried away
- ^ Russell & Norvig (2003,第960-961页)
- ^ 166.0 166.1 166.2 Singularity, transhumanism:
- ^
Joseph Weizenbaum's critique of AI:
- Weizenbaum 1976
- Crevier 1993,第132−144页
- McCorduck 2004,第356-373页
- Russell & Norvig 2003,第961页
- ^ Quoted in McCorduck (2004,第401页)
References
- Major AI textbooks
- See also A.I. Textbook survey
- Luger, George; Stubblefield, William. Artificial Intelligence: Structures and Strategies for Complex Problem Solving 5th. The Benjamin/Cummings Publishing Company, Inc. 2004. ISBN 0-8053-4780-1.
- Nilsson, Nils. Artificial Intelligence: A New Synthesis. Morgan Kaufmann Publishers. 1998. ISBN 978-1-55860-467-4.
- Template:Russell Norvig 2003
- Poole, David; Mackworth, Alan; Goebel, Randy. Computational Intelligence: A Logical Approach. New York: Oxford University Press. 1998.
- Winston, Patrick Henry. Artificial Intelligence. Reading, Massachusetts: Addison-Wesley. 1984. ISBN 0201082594.
- History of AI
- Other sources
- ACM, (Association of Computing Machinery). ACM Computing Classification System: Artificial intelligence. 1998 [2007-08-30].
- Aleksander, Igor, Artificial Neuroconsciousness: An Update, IWANN, 1995 BibTex Internet Archive
- Brooks, Rodney. Elephants Don't Play Chess (PDF). Robotics and Autonomous Systems. 1990, 6: 3–15 [2007-08-30]. doi:10.1016/S0921-8890(05)80025-9..
- Buchanan, Bruce G. A (Very) Brief History of Artificial Intelligence (PDF). AI Magazine. Winter 2005: 53–60 [2007-08-30].
- Dennett, Daniel. Consciousness Explained. The Penguin Press. 1991. ISBN 0-7139-9037-6.
- Dreyfus, Hubert. What Computers Can't Do. New York: MIT Press. 1972. ISBN 0060110821.
- Dreyfus, Hubert. What Computers Still Can't Do. New York: MIT Press. 1979. ISBN 0262041340.
- Dreyfus, Hubert; Dreyfus, Stuart. Mind over Machine: The Power of Human Intuition and Expertise in the Era of the Computer. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. 1986. ISBN 0029080606.
- Edelman, Gerald. Gerald Edelman - Neural Darwinism and Brain-based Devices. Talking Robots. 23 November 2007.
- Forster, Dion. Self validating consciousness in strong artificial intelligence: An African theological contribution. (PDF). Pretoria: University of South Africa. 2006.
- Gladwell, Malcolm. Blink. New York: Little, Brown and Co. 2005. ISBN 0-316-17232-4.
- Haugeland, John. Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. 1985. ISBN 0-262-08153-9.
- Hawkins, Jeff; Blakeslee, Sandra. On Intelligence. New York, NY: Owl Books. 2004. ISBN 0-8050-7853-3.
- Hofstadter, Douglas. Gödel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid. New York, NY: Vintage Books. 1979. ISBN 0394745027.
- Howe, J. Artificial Intelligence at Edinburgh University: a Perspective. November 1994. 已忽略未知参数
|retrieval-date=
(帮助). - Kahneman, Daniel; Slovic, D.; Tversky, Amos. Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. New York: Cambridge University Press. 1982. ISBN 0521284147.
- Kolata, G. How can computers get common sense?. Science. 1982, 217 (217): 1237–1238. doi:10.1126/science.217.4566.1237.
- Kurzweil, Ray. The Age of Spiritual Machines. Penguin Books. 1999. ISBN 0-670-88217-8.
- Kurzweil, Ray. The Singularity is Near. Penguin Books. 2005. ISBN 0-670-03384-7.
- Lakoff, George. Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal About the Mind. University of Chicago Press. 1987. ISBN 0-226-46804-6.
- Lakoff, George; Núñez, Rafael E. Where Mathematics Comes From: How the Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics into Being. Basic Books. 2000. ISBN 0-465-03771-2..
- Lenat, Douglas; Guha, R. V. Building Large Knowledge-Based Systems. Addison-Wesley. 1989. ISBN 0201517523.
- Lighthill, Professor Sir James. Artificial Intelligence: a paper symposium. Science Research Council. 1973.
|contribution=
被忽略 (帮助) - Lucas, John. Minds, Machines and Gödel. Anderson, A.R. (编). Minds and Machines. 1961. 已忽略未知参数
|retrieval-date=
(帮助) - Maker, Meg Houston. AI@50: AI Past, Present, Future. Dartmouth College. 2006 [16 October 2008].
- McCarthy, John; Minsky, Marvin; Rochester, Nathan; Shannon, Claude. A Proposal for the Dartmouth Summer Research Project on Artificial Intelligence. 1955. 已忽略未知参数
|retrieval-date=
(帮助). - McCarthy, John; Hayes, P. J. Some philosophical problems from the standpoint of artificial intelligence. Machine Intelligence. 1969, 4: 463–502. 已忽略未知参数
|retrieval-date=
(帮助) - Minsky, Marvin. Computation: Finite and Infinite Machines. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall. 1967. ISBN 0131654497.
- Minsky, Marvin. The Emotion Machine. New York, NY: Simon & Schusterl. 2006. ISBN 0-7432-7663-9.
- Moravec, Hans. The Role of Raw Power in Intelligence. 1976. 已忽略未知参数
|retrieval-date=
(帮助) - Moravec, Hans. Mind Children. Harvard University Press. 1988. ISBN 0674576160.
- NRC, (United States National Research Council). Developments in Artificial Intelligence. Funding a Revolution: Government Support for Computing Research. National Academy Press. 1999.
- Needham, Joseph. Science and Civilization in China: Volume 2. Caves Books Ltd. 1986.
- Newell, Allen; Simon, H. A. GPS: A Program that Simulates Human Thought. Feigenbaum, E.A.; Feldman, J. (编). Computers and Thought. McGraw-Hill. 1963. 已忽略未知参数
|publisher-place=
(帮助) - Newell, Allen; Simon, H. A. Communications of the ACM 19 (3). 1976.
|contribution=
被忽略 (帮助). - Nilsson, Nils, Artificial Intelligence Prepares for 2001 (PDF), AI Magazine, 1983, 1 (1), Presidential Address to the Association for the Advancement of Artificial Intelligence.
- Searle, John. Minds, Brains and Programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 1980, 3 (3): 417–457.
- Searle, John. Mind, language and society. New York, NY: Basic Books. 1999. ISBN 0465045219. OCLC 231867665 43689264 请检查
|oclc=
值 (帮助). - Shapiro, Stuart C. Artificial Intelligence. Shapiro, Stuart C. (编). Encyclopedia of Artificial Intelligence (PDF) 2nd. New York: John Wiley. 1992: 54–57. ISBN 0471503061.
- Simon, H. A. The Shape of Automation for Men and Management. New York: Harper & Row. 1965.
- Template:Turing 1950.
- van der Walt, Christiaan; Bernard, Etienne. Data characteristics that determine classifier performance (PDF). 2006 [5 August 2009].
- Wason, P. C.; Shapiro, D. Reasoning. Foss, B. M. (编). New horizons in psychology. Harmondsworth: Penguin. 1966.
- Weizenbaum, Joseph. Computer Power and Human Reason. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman & Company. 1976. ISBN 0716704641.
Further reading
- R. Sun & L. Bookman, (eds.), Computational Architectures: Integrating Neural and Symbolic Processes. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Needham, MA. 1994.
- Margaret Boden, Mind As Machine, Oxford University Press, 2006
- John Johnston, (2008) "The Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI", MIT Press
- Courtney Boyd Myers ed. (2009). The AI Report. Forbes June 2009
External links
- What Is AI? — An introduction to artificial intelligence by AI founder John McCarthy.
- Richmond Thomason. Logic and Artificial Intelligence. 扎尔塔, 爱德华·N (编). 《斯坦福哲学百科全书》.
- 开放目录项目中的“AI”
- AI Topics — A large directory of links and other resources maintained by the Association for the Advancement of Artificial Intelligence, the leading organization of academic AI researchers.